Austin can be tough going. The handout should help you distinguish
between his main points and those that are digressions.
Austin’s theory is that laws are commands. Today’s class concerns
several problems with the theory.
Not all laws fit the model of commands; some appear to be more
like instructions.
Having an obligation is not generally thought to be the same
thing as being threatened with a sanction.
Judges often decide cases based on what is called “customary law.”
This does not seem to come from the commands of a sovereign.
I think it is possible for Austin to give answers to these problems.
Another author we are going to read, H.L.A. Hart, develops his theory as
an alternative to Austin’s. Hart is going to maintain that his theory
has superior ways of addressing all three points.
Commands
Austin thought in trees. He liked to begin with a root concept and
then subdivide it into branches until he had identified the concept he
wished to analyze. So, for example, there are two branches off of the
root concept of “expressions of desire:” requests and commands. While
they are grammatically similar, they are different because commands come
with sanctions. Laws will be one of the sub-branches of commands.
Commands, according to Austin, always involve three things (Austin [1832] 1995,
24):
a desire concerning someone’s behavior
an expression of that desire
a sanction, threatened harm for non-compliance
The first two elements are common between requests and commands while
the last one distinguishes commands from requests.
Here is an expression that looks like a command: “plug in
the toaster.” This will be one of our first topics of discussion. Is
that a command, as Austin understands it, or not?
Duties
For Austin, the terms “command,” “sanction,” and “duty” (or
“obligation”) are all defined in terms of one another. To receive a
command is equivalent to being threatened with a sanction and being
threatened with a sanction is equivalent to having a duty (Austin [1832] 1995,
22–24). This, according to Austin, is why people are obliged to
obey the law.
A second topic of discussion concerns the apparent divergence between
this understanding of “duty” and the ordinary one. Think about cases
where you owe a debt to someone else. Would you owe the debt even if you
could not be threatened with a sanction? Conversely, is being threatened
with a sanction enough to put you in debt to someone?
Sovereigns
A sovereign, according to Austin, is someone that the “bulk” of the
population is in the habit of obeying while not being in the habit of
obeying anyone else (Austin [1832] 1995, 166).
Think about cases that seem to diverge from his definition:
sovereigns that do not have this quality or entities that do but do not
count as sovereigns.
Customary law
When judges say things like “like cases should be decided alike” or
“no one should profit from their own wrongdoing,” they are sometimes not
drawing on anything that could be traced to a sovereign’s command.
Instead, they are referring to what is sometimes called “customary
law.”
Is customary law part of the law or not?
Austin could say “my theory says it has to come from the sovereign’s
commands, this doesn’t, so it’s not law.” But he doesn’t say that. He
says that the customary law is “judge-made law” (Austin [1832] 1995, 35). How do
judges make law? They get the authority to do so from the sovereign.
Main ideas
Here is a list of key terms in Austin’s theory that you should be
able to explain after today’s class.
Command
Duty (or obligation)
Sovereign
Also, it wouldn’t hurt to know how he accommodates customary law;
remember the phrase “judge made law.”
References
Austin, John. (1832) 1995. The Province of Jurisprudence
Determined. Edited by Wilfrid E. Rumble. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511521546.