Today’s reading presents what Hobbes calls the laws of nature. This
is his moral philosophy. He seeks to make two points about the laws of
nature:
They are valuable because they are the rules that people have to
follow in order to live in peace.
What they require individuals to do depends on how others
behave.
You can see how the two points are related. If the laws of nature are
rules that people have to follow if there is to be peace and others are
not following the laws, then there will be no peace and so no point in
following the laws yourself.
You might ask “Why does he have a moral theory at all? Isn’t this
political philosophy?” And that would be a very good question. Why not
just go straight from “anarchy (aka the state of nature) is bad” to “the
state (aka the commonwealth) would be better”?
What is in chapters 14 and 15?
People in the state of nature are not stupid. At least, they are no
more stupid than we are. There is an obvious solution to their problem:
make a non-aggression pact! I promise not to attack you so long as you
do not attack me and vice versa. That would take care of
diffidence and “anticipation.” Once they have that worked out, they can
make some property rules to make progress on competition as a cause of
conflict. And if they are really ambitious they can make some
rules about the use of violence to dampen fighting motivated by
glory.
Chapters fourteen and fifteen are about how that might work. The most
important part concerns what Hobbes calls covenants. These are promises
in which one side is trusted to do its part in the future. If I say “pay
me tuition in August and I will deliver a lecture on Hobbes in
February,” I have made a covenant: you have to wait for me to do my
part.
More importantly, if I say “I will not sneak up on you at night so
long as you do not threaten me,” I have also made a covenant. You are
relying on my keeping my end tonight, tomorrow night, the next night,
and, well, every night into the indefinite future. We probably want to
throw in the daytime as well. You get the idea.
Chapter fifteen also has some rules about maintaining a peace
established by covenants. There are rules about behavior that could
upset the peace in ways that are not specific enough to cover in an
agreement. For example, you should show gratitude and not take more than
you need (15.16-17). There are rules about enforcing the rules in ways
that will not cause the system to collapse in cycles of revenge
(15.18-19). And there are rules for using arbitrators to settle disputes
about deciding when the rules have been broken and about how to punish
those who break the rules (15.23f).
In sum, what we have here are rules for establishing peace without
the state. They are laws “of nature” rather than laws of the
commonwealth.
So why do we need the state?
If the laws of nature are so great, why do we need the state?
Well, remember the second point: what the laws of nature require
depends on how others behave. If others are not keeping the laws of
nature, you do not have to do so either. Hobbes is quite clear about
this: see 15.36. In the state of nature, you cannot count on anyone’s
keeping the laws of nature.
To see why, let’s go back to the problem of diffidence. People in the
state of nature are in what is called a prisoner’s dilemma (I will
explain the name in an appendix below).
Here is a representation of that.
There is only one stable set of choices here: the northwest box
(Anticipate, Anticipate). Suppose they start in the southeast box (Wait,
Wait). Row will move to the northeast box (Anticipate, Wait) because
first is better than second. Then Column will move from the northeast
box to the northwest box because third is better than fourth.
We would reach the same result going the other way. Suppose we start
in the southeast box (Wait, Wait) as before and that Column moves to the
southwest box (Wait, Anticipate) because first is better than second.
Row will push into the northwest box (Anticipate, Anticipate) because
third is better than fourth.
In essence, whichever one is getting the fourth best outcome from
waiting while the other is anticipating will switch to anticipating
instead.
That is the problem: they are in a situation where each of them has
an incentive to begin a war with the others. The obvious solution is to
establish a non-aggression pact. I promise not to attack you by surprise
so long as you do the same for me. Now, having made our covenant, we
each face a question every day: should I keep it or break it?
Guess what the incentive structure looks like!
If we did not trust one another before we made the non-aggression
pact, it is hard to see how we are going to trust one another to keep
it. Remember that the cost of misplaced trust can be very high. It can
be the last mistake you ever make. (If that does not sound so bad, think
about it for a second.)
Without a working non-aggression pact, the rest of the laws do not
matter very much.
The upshot is that we are not getting out of war in the state of
nature without an actual state to threaten us if we ever try to leave
the southeast box. That’s the only way it is going to work.
The good news is that once we have a state in place, we get to enjoy
the kind of life made possible by the laws of nature. Hobbes assumes
that most people will comply if they can do so safely. And if they try
to cheat, the state will be there to suggest they reconsider. In that
sense, morality depends on the state.
Questions
If morality depends on the state, does that mean that nothing is
wrong among people who do not live in a state with one another? It sure
seems to (see 14.4). That is hard to swallow. You cannot do
anything wrong to another person until you share a state?
Yikes.
You will be relieved to know that he wavers on this point. For
example, he was convinced that cruelty was always wrong and he took a
couple not very convincing stabs at reconciling this with his theory
(see chapter 15, paragraph 19 for one).
Hobbes also wavers on the central case for his theory: covenants. He
says that covenants are invalid when one party to the covenant fears
that the other will not do its part (14.18).
You would think that this is always true in the state of nature: you
always fear the other side will break its word and no covenants are
valid. Hobbes says this himself (15.3, for instance).
But he also says the opposite. For instance, if you are captured in a
war and agree to pay a ransom provided you are released, your agreement
is valid and you are obliged to pay (14.27). Hobbes also takes a shot at
a Ring of Gyges kind of case involving a character he calls the Fool
(15.4-5). The Fool asks why he should keep his covenants if he can get
away with breaking them. Hobbes tries to show that he should keep them.
The idea is that if the Fool does not keep his word he will not have the
allies that he needs to survive in the state of nature. Potential allies
will think “he is promising to defend me if I am attacked provided I
promise to defend him if he is attacked, but I do not believe that he
will do what he promises so there is no point to my making this
covenant.” This is OK as far as it goes but it does not really explain
why the Fool should keep his covenant if he knows he can get
away with breaking it. But leave the question of how successful the
argument is to one side. The attempt to explain why people should keep
their covenants in the state of nature makes sense only if covenants can
be valid in the state of nature. Otherwise, there is nothing to keep! To
put it another way, the Fool’s potential allies are obviously keeping
their covenants. If they were not, there would be no cost to being
excluded from an alliance with them.
Why is he so wobbly about this?
Main Points
Why covenants are an obvious solution to the problems faced by
people in the state of nature.
Why covenants are obviously not a solution to the problems faced
by people in the state of nature.
Why you can make a case for thinking that Hobbes did think
covenants were valid in the state of nature.
Extra: Why is it called a prisoner’s dilemma?
The name “prisoner’s dilemma” comes from a case used to illustrate
it. A prosecutor offers two prisoners a deal. “If you give me enough
evidence to convict the other guy, he will get an eight year sentence
and you will go free. If neither of you give me any evidence, I will be
able to convict both of you on a lesser charge that carries a two year
sentence. But if both of you give me enough evidence to convict each
other, you will each get five year sentences.”
When people are in a prisoner’s dilemma, there is only one stable
solution: the northwest (upper left) one. This reflects the fact that
they each have what is called a dominant strategy, namely, a choice that
is better no matter what the other one does.
In this case, the dominant strategy is to talk. For instance, if
Prisoner C (C for column) decides to talk, Prisoner R (R for row) will
be better off talking too because a five year sentence (-5) is better
than an eight year sentence (-8). And if Prisoner C decides to stay
quiet, Prisoner R will be better off talking since no sentence (-0) is
better than a two year sentence (-2). If we did the same thing with
Prisoner C, we would get the same answer: it makes sense to talk no
matter what Prisoner R does. Since both are better off talking than
staying quiet no matter what the other one does, they will wind up in
the northwest box even though they would obviously be better off in the
southeast box.
References
Hobbes, Thomas. (1651) 1993. Leviathan. Edited by Mark C.
Rooks. British Philosophy: 1600-1900. Charlottesville, VA: InteLex
Corporation.